Kevin Yuill writes:
Last week, the Court of Appeal in London rejected an appeal by two
plaintiffs on the question of whether severely disabled and dying people could
be given assistance to end their lives.
The appeal, brought by the widow of the late Tony
Nicklinson, a victim of locked-in syndrome, and by Paul Lamb, a 57-year-old former
builder who has been paralysed for the past 23 years, was based on two
arguments.
First, Lamb and Nicklinson argued on the basis of necessity; in
other words, to protect medical practitioners from murder charges, it could be
argued that ending the life of a severely disabled or dying person was necessary
to prevent intolerable suffering. Second, Nicklinson and Lamb argued that the
current murder laws are incompatible with the Human Rights Act.
It came as no surprise that Lamb and Nicklinson’s
appeal should be rejected. Judges have repeatedly ruled that it is for
parliament to change the law over assisted suicide, not the courts.
However, a third man, known only as Martin, asked
for clarification as to whether medical staff accompanying him to Switzerland
to a suicide organisation would be subject to prosecution. The court gave
Martin permission to take his case to the Supreme Court.
How do these cases change the existing situation?
The judgment that parliament alone can decide on issues related to the right to
die is entirely positive. As the Lord Chief Justice noted, parliament is the
‘conscience of the nation’, acknowledging the far-reaching moral consequences
of any decision allowing assisted suicide. It is correct that Parliament should
be the institution to consider such a change.
At another level, campaigners might feel that
they are chipping away at a law that will inevitably shift at some stage. In
recent years, assisted suicide has been legalised in a small number of US
states, and euthanasia has been legalised in Luxembourg and Belgium, too. While
the law is hardly changing at breakneck speed in the UK, the supporters of
assisted suicide and euthanasia may view such changes in other jurisdictions as
cause for optimism.
The cases of Nicklinson, Lamb and Martin also
raise the inherent difficulty with a change in the law. How to do it? Do we
allow individuals to decide for themselves whether or not they are ‘suffering
unbearably’ or do we set specific criteria under which we deem suffering a
reason to assist in an individual’s death? If so, what criteria? No one has yet
answered such questions; nor are they likely to be able to answer them
categorically.
On one hand, Dignity in Dying, the highest-profile
organisation campaigning for a change in the law, does not support the
particular change requested by Nicklinson and Lamb. It feels that only
terminally ill patients with six (or perhaps 12) months left to live should be
allowed to have help to die. Severe disability alone would not qualify.
On the other, Andrew Copson, chair of the British
Humanist Association – forgetting that this issue is not one of religious
versus secular values – lent Lamb and Nicklinson his vocal support. Presumably,
Copson believes either that all people should be able to have help to commit
suicide based on their own assessment of whether their lives are worth living,
or he believes that the lives of disabled persons are worth less than the lives
of others. It would be very interesting to find out which, assuming that Copson
has thought through the issue at all.
These are deep moral questions. The Court of
Appeal is absolutely right to point to parliament rather than the courts as the
conscience of the nation. However, this will not be the last we hear about this
question. Let’s hope it can now be debated in the open by representatives of
the British electorate rather than ruled on by appointed judges.
No comments:
Post a Comment