Amy Davidson writes:
Should we just stop talking about any form of
amnesty for Edward Snowden, because he swore an oath and broke it?
In a piece
for Slate titled “Why Snowden Won’t (And Shouldn’t) Get Clemency,” Fred Kaplan
mentions my suggestion, in a piece for the site, that Jimmy Carter’s pardoning of
Vietnam draft dodgers offers “a useful parallel” when thinking of the legal
situation of Edward Snowden. Kaplan writes:
This suggestion is mind-boggling on several
levels. Among other things, Snowden signed an oath, as a condition of his
employment as an NSA contractor, not to disclose classified information, and
knew the penalties for violating the oath.
The young men who evaded the draft,
either by fleeing to Canada or serving jail terms, did so in order to avoid
taking an oath to fight a war that they opposed—a war that was over, and widely
reviled, by the time that Carter pardoned them.
There are no such extenuating circumstances
favoring forgiveness of Snowden.
This is an odd and flawed argument—logically and
legally, but also historically and factually. The errors illustrate how we tend
to misremember the past, and misjudge its passions when comparing them to our
own.
There is also the question of why an oath matters, in a different way than a serious federal law like the Selective Service Act—but first the facts.
There is also the question of why an oath matters, in a different way than a serious federal law like the Selective Service Act—but first the facts.
To begin with, did Snowden sign “an oath…not to
disclose classified information”?
He says that he did not, and that does not
appear to have been contradicted. Snowden told
the Washington Post’s Barton Gellman that the document he
signed, as what Kaplan calls “a condition of his employment,” was Standard
Form 312, a contract in which the signatory says he will “accept” the
terms, rather than swearing to them.
By signing it, Snowden agreed that he was
aware that there were federal laws against disclosing classified information.
But the penalties for violating agreement alone are civil: for example, the
government can go after any book royalties he might get for publishing secrets.
Snowden did take an oath—the Oath of Office, or
appointment affidavit, given to all federal employees:
I will support and defend the Constitution of the
United States against all enemies, foreign and domestic; that I will bear true
faith and allegiance to the same; that I take this obligation freely, without
any mental reservation or purpose of evasion; and that I will well and
faithfully discharge the duties of the office on which I am about to enter. So
help me God.
Now, some would argue (and it would have to be an
argument, not an elision) that he violated this oath in revealing what he did;
Snowden told Gellman that the revelations were how he kept it—protecting the
Constitution from the officials at the N.S.A., which was assaulting it. Either
way this is just not an oath, on the face of it, about disclosing classified
information.
What about the draft dodgers? Kaplan considers it
an extenuating factor that they acted before taking an oath to join the
military.
Legally speaking, this is circular: the criminal act in draft-dodging
was refusing to join the military. How could it be extenuated by the
fact that it took place? In any event, except when talking about, say, mail
fraud, the notion that the comparative severity of crimes can be measured by
the number of papers signed beforehand is a strange one. Murderers don’t
usually sign non-murder agreements.
Still, as it happens, a lot of dodgers did
put their names on a lot of documents along the way. Some tried every trick in
the book to get a deferment, including submitting false statements. Even before
being examined by a draft board, they would have had to fill out Form 100, a
questionnaire to help determine their draft classification.
This is no civil
contract; the signature line mentions criminal penalties, and there are bonus
warnings for anyone seeking conscientious objector status. In that sense, it is
more stringent than Form 312. If by “oath” Kaplan just means a harshly
worded document, they both count.
Young men tried to evade the draft by, among
other things, lying on this form. Some were prosecuted for doing so, and then
some were pardoned for the act.
Carter’s pardon was broad: you didn’t have to
show that you’d opposed the war. Not everybody who tried to get out of the
draft was motivated by principle, though draft resistance was integral to the
movement to end the war. And I do think, lest this be misconstrued, was a just
cause deserving a pardon.
There’s still the question of oaths. Did all of
the young men we, as a country, forgave manage to “avoid taking an oath,” as
Kaplan writes? Soldiers do take an oath, to
support and defend the Constitution and obey their officers. Snowden would
have taken this during his brief time in the military. What about deserters,
who broke it?
Carter’s pardon did not include deserters. But
deserters had a chance under an even earlier clemency offer, which President
Ford extended for a several months starting in September, 1974—when the war was
not entirely over, and some Americans and more Vietnamese were still dying.
It
had conditions, as any deal with Snowden certainly would; those who hadn’t
served time in prison had to work in public-service jobs, for example in a
hospital, for two years. (Sports-historical footnote: the chairman of the
clemency board was Charles Goodell, whose son Roger is now commissioner of the
N.F.L.)
Still, there was mercy.
In other words, the historical reality appears to
be pretty much the opposite of what Kaplan writes: Snowden, as far as one can
tell, didn’t take an “oath” not to disclose classified information, and some
Vietnam-era deserters who received clemency did take and violate their own
oath.
Introducing the plan, Ford
spoke of his hope that it would be a step toward “a calmer and cooler
appreciation of our individual rights and responsibilities.” That is as a
pretty clear statement of what we can also hope to get from the Snowden case.
Ford’s clemency offer came a month after he’d
pardoned Nixon—a man of many oaths. A Times story from 1974 quoted Ford
as saying, at a press conference, “Well, the only connection between those two
cases is the effort that I made in the one to heal the wounds involving charges
against Mr. Nixon and my honest and conscientious effort to heal the wounds for
those who had deserted military service or dodged the draft.”
Those wounds were still unhealed during the
Carter Presidency, and, decades later, some never have closed up. Kaplan writes
that the war was, by 1977, “widely reviled,” but so, in many quarters, were
draft evaders.
Whether Bill Clinton and George Bush had legally avoided being
sent overseas was still a contentious issue in both men’s Presidencies. What
if, at the time, we were still jailing and hunting down fugitive draft evaders?
We are missing something about the history and use of pardons and amnesties,
here and abroad, if we act as though they only come into play after all the
fight has gone out of an issue.
Bush’s father pardoned half a dozen officials
(and oath-of-office takers) for crimes related to the Iran-Contra scandal,
among them Caspar Weinberger, the former Secretary of Defense, for the
promise-based crime of perjury.
Not all amnesties and pardons are good for the
country—tacit ones, like those for torture in the war on terror, can preclude
necessary debate.
But it’s a fantasy to say that no one in America has ever
been allowed to avoid going to jail for a serious crime when it is seen as best
for the country, and sometimes when it is not.
As I’ve written before, the
government could further its own practical interests by means of an amnesty,
pardon, or plea bargain, too—there are ways Snowden could help.
Similarly,
Snowden’s presence in Russia, of all places, is seen as a dirty affront. We
might, then, want to get him out of there, which is what he appears to want,
too. Joe Nocera has a good column on the case for Brazil.
Kaplan says that some of what Snowden revealed
isn’t useful for Americans to know; the extent to which that is so (and is
harmful) is debatable.
But Kaplan oddly includes on his list things like the
worldwide collection of cell-location data, which has
entangled and violated the rights of Americans. He also errs in writing
that the revelations don’t involve “any documents detailing the
cyber-operations of any other countries,” something Britain’s
GCHQ would be surprised to hear.
Nevertheless, there is no question at
this point that the usefulness has been great, as even the President would
concede.
That brings us back to a slight mystery: the
dispositive quality of oathiness. Why is the idea that Snowden took a
particular oath so often brought up as an argument against some deal that would
allow him to come back to America and stay out of prison?
It’s not really about
his legal jeopardy. Of course Snowden broke laws—that’s why we’re even
having a conversation about amnesty. If he hadn’t, he wouldn’t need it. Saying
that it’s ridiculous to talk about amnesty when he’s committed serious crimes
is like saying there’s no point in talking about divorce because someone is
married.
Bringing up the oath point is really meant as a
commentary on Snowden’s character. It is itself an oath, in another sense—an
interjection, an outburst of anger. There are a lot of people in the
government, and public, who are simply dismayed by Snowden’s actions, and by
everything about him, down to his glasses and haircut.
The oath he swore was
supposed to be humbling, and he is presumptuous. The discussions about him
become choked with rage—even as the conversation he alone started and made
possible becomes ever louder and clearer.
No comments:
Post a Comment