Matt Bruenig of the liberal think tank Demos
recently enlisted
John Locke’s First Treatise in making the case for “freedom from
want,” which provoked a combox and Twitter rejoinder from Cato’s Jason
Kuznicki. Here’s the
passage Bruenig quotes:
a man can
no more justly make use of another’s necessity to force him to become his
vassal, by with-holding that relief God requires him to afford to the wants of
his brother, than he that has more strength can seize upon a weaker, master him
to his obedience, and with a dagger at his throat offer him death or slavery.
Kuznicki responded by invoking the
Second
Treatise as a development of Locke’s thought—which Bruenig
finds problematic, noting
that the First Treatise was actually composed later. (A full account
of how and when the two treatises were written gets complicated.) In any case,
Kuznicki need not have looked so far afield, when Locke’s elaboration of his
thought is to be found just one paragraph later:
Should any
one make so perverse an use of God’s blessings poured on him with a liberal
hand; should any one be cruel and uncharitable to that extremity; yet all this
would not prove that propriety in land, even in this case, gave any authority
over the persons of men, but only that compact might; since the authority of
the rich proprietor, and the subjection of the needy beggar, began not from the
possession of the lord, but the consent of the poor man, who preferred being
his subject to starving. And the man he thus submits to, can pretend to no more
power over him, than he has consented to, upon compact.
Read on and you’ll find that Locke brings this
back to a refutation of those (like Filmer) who ground political authority in
God’s grant of the earth to some particular lineage. What Locke is at pains to
explain here is that owning land does not mean one owns the people on the
land—they may not be reduced to slaves; they also may not be reduced to feudal
vassals—but rather whatever legitimate governing there is must derive from
the subject’s consent at some level.
Libertarians who don’t like contractarianism
object to Locke precisely because of this myth: whether or not real-world
consent is given, Locke builds his system so that consent is invoked as a
justification for authority. These passages show Locke pulling the same trick
with respect to economic power: the renter is subject to the owner not because
the owner has inherent absolute power over his land and what’s on it but
because the renter is in effect consenting by renting.
The renter or the
citizen may be under the authority of the owner or government, but he is only
under that authority because he consents to it—thus the weaker party remains
free in the way that matters most to Locke, if not to us. This right of consent
(or not) is inalienable, which has implications for Locke’s larger scheme of
politics and political economy, and it’s not nothing. But it’s far short of
guaranteeing what a modern liberal is likely to mean by “freedom from want.”
Locke obviously is concerned about material
needs, however, and believes that every man has a right to have those needs
met, including by other people. The thing that has to be considered carefully
is how those needs are to be met. There are at least two
possibilities: other people can set aside enough wilderness—in North America,
say, or the English commons—that
any man whose needs are unmet at present may have use of open resources and
thus provide for himself.
Another possibility, however, is the one brought to
the reader’s attention as Locke points out that the vast lands of North America
are rather poor, whereas the very limited, already homesteaded lands of England
are rich. To supply a surplus sufficient for everyone, then, what’s important
is not open land but enclosed
land: private property whose surpluses may be obtained by the needy through
consensual exchanges.
How big a role political arrangements (which are another
outcome of consent) may play in this, either in Locke’s own view or in a modern
adaptation of his theory, is open to some interpretation.
Without delving into much more detail for now,
suffice to say that libertarians and modern welfare-state liberals alike may be
troubled by a closer examination of Locke’s views of government and property.
Consider, for example, Joseph
Stromberg’s provocative reading of Locke as arch-imperialist:
No stranger
to mercantilism and colonial imperialism, Locke nevertheless argued that land
is not rightly acquired by conquest unless it has been lying idle. This exception is extremely important, since
Locke artfully fitted his “natural” right to property to English Protestant
practices. Non-Europeans need not apply.
Locke conceded that God had given land
to mankind in common. On the other hand, the “industrious and rational”
can—indeed must—prevent its being “wasted.” They can “mix” their labor with
land to acquire it but must maximize the
product. Anyone failing to maximize could rightfully be dispossessed—Indians in
America, non-enclosing peasants at home.
In effect, Locke promoted freedom for
a minority of industrious Englishmen—a freedom to be paid for through constant
growth premised in part on overseas empire.
(A similar interpretation is developed in great
detail is here.)
There was a religious side to this colonialism as
well. Recall that Locke’s toleration
did not extend to Catholics. This was in part ye olde English prejudice—think Titus Oates and that kind of
thing—but there’s also a deep Protestant sectarian basis for Locke’s ideas
about consent and legitimate institutionalization of authority. Catholicism was
not just historically incompatible with English ways, but Locke’s theory is
very particularly a politics wedded to a religious tendency.
All of which is to say that there are many layers
to Locke. His notions of liberty may not, on examination, be for everyone.
""Locke conceded that God had given land to mankind in common"".
ReplyDeleteIn which case, there is no such thing as private property and therefore no such thing as freedom.
How dare these people co-opt God in support of their totalitarian ideals.
You need to read an awful lot more. Augustine and Aquinas, for a start. Or the Bible, in fact.
ReplyDeleteThe Marxist idea that land is held in common is antithetical to the notion of private property, without which liberty doesn't exist.
ReplyDeleteMiliband's pronouncements on the subject (of a piece with his support for a state-shackled press) indicate that he is an enemy of liberty.
You genuinely have no idea what you are talking about. One sincerely does not know where to begin with you.
ReplyDeleteA certain Polish Pope grew in the kind of country where the state could seize your land if you didn't follow its diktats.
ReplyDeleteAnd, of course, the kind of country where the press and the state were one and the same thing.
Since you've never lived under it (and neither had Miliband's dad) I can forgive your hilarious ignorance.
And he promulgated the Catechism of the Catholic Church, which I suggest that you read on precisely this question.
ReplyDelete