Angus Kennedy writes:
UK foreign secretary William Hague, in threatening
recently to storm the Ecuadorian embassy in London and arrest Julian Assange,
displays the same degree of contempt for national sovereignty that Western
nations have shown repeatedly since the end of the Cold War. The examples of
this contempt are legion, from invading countries to bring about regime change,
to the unelected officials of the Troika (the European Commission, European
Central Bank and the IMF) lecturing and threatening Greece into sacrificing
itself on the altar of the interests of the European Union. And in each case,
the core principles of national self-determination and of democratic sovereignty,
once championed by Woodrow Wilson and Lenin alike, are more likely today to be
attacked as the fig leaves of dictators.
Thierry Baudet’s The Significance of Borders
is a rare counter to such views. A controversial Dutch columnist for NRC
Handelsblad, a lawyer and historian at the University of Leiden, Baudet
argues that representative government and the rule of law is impossible without
the nation state. But today, he argues, the nation is under attack from two
directions.
First it is under attack from supranationalism,
that is, from institutions like the European Court of Human Rights, the UN
Security Council, and, most dramatically, the European Union. So while nations
retain sovereignty at a formal level, increasing degrees of ‘material
sovereignty’ have been acquired by supranational organisations. Baudet argues,
for instance, that the official aim of the EU ‘is the negation of the concept
of statehood’, because the nation state is held responsible, most notably by
German theorists, for war. The EU’s immanent federalist logic leads to the
necessary extension of its bureaucratic power (taking more and more countries into
its orbit). Or – as an illustration of the attack on the democratic
basis of national sovereignty – take the contempt in which the ECHR holds
Britain for denying convicted prisoners the right to vote: this despite the
fact that parliament voted 234 votes to 22 against the proposal. It seems the
ECHR is happy to demand Britain change laws upheld by its own democracy.
Second, self-government is also under attack from
below. Firstly, in the form of multiculturalism and its official
support, legal pluralism (where the law is applied with cultural ‘sensitivity’
rather than justly). Secondly, from cultural diversity, which rejects the idea
of a British or a Dutch identity in favour of overlapping multiple, provisional
and lightly held, identities. Baudet gives the example of the Dutch crown
princess, Máxima, who declared in 2007 that ‘the Dutch identity does not
exist’, that the world has ‘open borders’ and that ‘it is not either-or. But
and-and.’ When royalty – once the very symbol of national sovereignty – refuses
to discriminate between citizens and outsiders, then even the most ardent
internationalist might begin to smell a rat.
As Baudet argues, without a community of interest,
a ‘we’, there is nothing. He notes that the ECHR outlaws ‘discrimination on any
ground such as sex, race, colour, language, religion, political or other
opinion, national or social origin, association with a national minority,
property, birth or other status’. Everyone must be treated equally. Baudet is
correct to point out that such a widely drawn attack on discrimination ‘must
necessarily implicate the citizens’ indifference towards those
criteria’. Any form of particularity, of which nationality is one, is denied in
the name of a totalising universality. The effect is not the widening of ‘minds
and sympathies’ but rather their ‘Balkanisation’. In the process, the law
becomes ‘no longer “ours” or “from within”, but from “out there”’. Our
responsibility is eroded and our capacity to decide for ourselves (however we
constitute that ‘we’) is further diminished, both at the level of the nation
state, historically the basis for constituting a self-governing ‘we’, and at
the level of the individual citizen.
The case of Hungary is a good example of how these
two trends – the supranational and the multicultural – come together to the
detriment of democracy and sovereignty. By backing the corrupt socialist
government of Ferenc Gyurcsany against the right-wing Fidesz and Jobbik parties
in 2010, the EU destabilised public life and actually fostered the very
nationalism it sets itself against. It didn’t just pour fuel on the fire of
populist reaction, but also blew on the flames by branding Hungary a savage
throwback to darker times. Most disturbingly, EU criticisms of Hungary ignore
the fact that Viktor Orbán’s Fidesz government was freely elected with a
massive majority.
However, Baudet’s book is open to criticism is on
two points. Firstly it understates the degree to which the dismantling of the
nation is actually a project of national elites. The nation is not being
attacked from without so much as from within. National politicians have long
sought refuge in Brussels from their own responsibility to make and drive
through policy. EU-blaming has always been a useful way of passing the buck for
unpopular decisions. Yet in hiding behind the EU or the ECHR, national
politicians share the very same contempt for sovereign democracy as Brussels.
One of the main reasons for this contempt is not
only the hostility to nationalism generated in the aftermath of the First World
War but also the defeat of the internal opposition to nationalism, represented
internally by the left, and externally by the Soviet Union. Nationalists won a
hollow victory by defeating the two poles against which a declaration of being
British or Dutch made sense. With the content of nationalism gone, there is no
way back. Neither plastic-flag waving nor opposition to supranationalism will
help. Traditions cannot simply be reinvented.
Baudet does correctly locate the problem as being
one of trying to steer a middle road through two concepts of the nation: the
radical Enlightenment concept of the nation as an act of the rational and
universalist will; and the Romantic concept of it, in Tzvetan Todorov’s phrase,
as ‘a community of “blood”’. Yet I am not convinced that Baudet’s path between
the two, ‘multicultural nationalism’, is that different to
multiculturalism. Arguing for genuine tolerance (which reserves the
right to judge and disapprove and to discriminate), rather than
multi-something, might be a better solution. It is also necessary to frame the
problem correctly. The danger is not, despite Baudet’s fears, that national
loyalties will be replaced with ‘tribal or religious’ loyalties: the danger is
that there will be no loyalty to any community.
Secondly Borders, while noting the problems
of being a ‘we’, makes little reference to those of being an ‘I’. As Albert
Camus put it in The Rebel: ‘I rebel – therefore we exist.’
Baudet will be aware from his own controversial position in Holland that to
dissent from the orthodoxy today is usually met with outraged offence: ‘You
can’t say that.’ So at the same time as there is a hostility to national
identity there is a parallel hostility to any identity which fails to conform
to type.
This is part of a much broader and deeper problem:
the erosion of the authority of the sovereign subject. And here is the paradox:
while the nation state has indeed lost authority, the state has simultaneously
acquired an unprecedented level of power to intervene in the hitherto sovereign
private sphere, from what we eat and drink to how we bring up our kids.
Baudet’s conclusion, his diagnosis, though, is on
the mark. We are stuck – stuck, that is, between past and future, between
tomorrow’s unaccountable super-EU and yesterday’s ‘we’. As Baudet puts it, ‘the
present, supranational “in between” concept of European integration with an EU
that is stuck somewhere halfway between a federation and mere intergovernmental
cooperation, is unsustainable’. Something must give. We must find a way to
resist those who presume to act on our behalf. In the process we must
rediscover what it means to be an individual today and what it means to be a
‘we’.
Just as it is necessary to defend the family and
our personal lives from state interference, so we must also defend our nations
from interference by those who do not represent us. One way of doing this is,
of course, to uphold the principle of national self-determination, to defend
nations like Syria from external intervention. Another way is to try to think
through what we value about where we live and how we interact. This requires,
in the first place, freedom – of the individual and of the people. As ever, we
must start at home, set off from where we are.
No comments:
Post a Comment